Iv российский философский конгресс

Вид материалаДоклад

Содержание


Grigorii Goutner (Russia). Comments on Rom Harre “Hybrid Psychology: The marriage of discourse analysis with neuroscience”
Наталия Смирнова (Россия). Феноменологическая концепция релевантности и ее значение для современной теории познания
Notes and references
Подобный материал:
1   ...   11   12   13   14   15   16   17   18   ...   25

Individualism and collectivism

The fact that some cognitive processes are both public and jointly conducted by more than one person, usually in a conversational interaction, rises the question of what sort of collectives are capable of cognition. There are two main kinds of groupings that appear as referents in psychological discourses. There are structured collectives, like families and other institutions which are self-maintaining groups held together by real relations, such as engaging in conversation. Then there are taxonomic or purely notional collectives, logical constructs tied together by sharing common properties. Such groups are so rarely related by any real relations that we can safely neglect the possibility. It should be obvious that only structured collectives can be the sites of group cognition. We find joint public cognitive processes in the life courses of families, research groups, sports teams and so on. Only to these does P-grammar analysis in terms of rules and intentional actions apply.

Persons are necessarily material in so far as singular embodiment is a necessary condition for personal identity. There is only one substance. But persons and the products of their symbolic activities, also materially realized as sounds and signs, form networks linked by intentional and normative relations, while molecular clusters are related causally. There is only one substance, but it supports two irreducibly different sets of relations.


References


Garfinkel, H. (1967) Studies in Ethnomethodology. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.

Parrott, W. G & Harré, R. (1998) The Emotions. London: Sage.

Polanyi. M. (1966) The Tacit Dimension. Garden City, NY: Doubleday.

Shweder, R. (1991) Thinking Through Cultures. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.


Григорий Гутнер (Россия). Комментарий к докладу Рома Харре

Grigorii Goutner (Russia). Comments on Rom Harre “Hybrid Psychology: The marriage of discourse analysis with neuroscience”


The following notes are not a detailed analysis of the Rom Harre’s paper. I shall only try to make some implications from it.

1. First of all, I want to pay attention on task/tool metaphor. I believe it to be very fruitful for description of cognitive activity. However, I believe also, that consistent use of this metaphor will lead us to such theory of cognition, which is rather alike to Cartesian one. If we consider something as a tool, we must presuppose somebody, who uses it. In other words, the idea of tool is strictly correlated with an idea of subject. The subject is not identical with the tool, because he/she is one who has various tools in his/her disposal, who is able to choose for some task an appropriate tool. Who is then the subject, which uses as tools hands, legs and brains? He is someone principally different from all these parts of body and, finally, from a whole body. This conclusion has much in common with the Cartesian concept of the subject of cognition. According to Descartes, I cannot consider myself as a body, because I am ‘res cogitans’. Descartes develops the procedure of the “radical doubt” which implies an alienation of body from mind. As a result, the body is considered as an object for some subject, for thinking one cardinally different from it. The task/tool metaphor also implies an alienation of body. As distinct from Descartes, the alienation makes it not an object, but an instrument of cognition. However, the subject of cognition appears to be rather alike the Cartesian one.

2. I believe, that the idea of ‘Hybrid Psychology’, which is developed in the paper, is incompatible with any materialistic approach to mind-body problem. It is evidently impossible to reduce any description of cognitive activity, which is made in terms of ‘P-grammar’, to some description of physical event, made in the terms of ‘M/O-grammar’. It is also impossible (as D. Davidson does) to consider ‘P-discourse’ as a supevenience of physical events. Main postulate of the Identity Theory presupposes a privileged status of discourses, which are developed in frames of M and O-grammars. In Hybrid Psychology, three discourses (M, O and P) must have an equal status. One may suppose, that all the three described three aspects of the same reality, which is, ultimately, nor physical neither mental. The main reason for the supposition is the specific status of the subject of cognition, implied by the ‘task/tool metaphor’. This subject is a reality in question. All the three discourses represent three different aspects of his/her cognitive activity.

3. Though three kinds of discourses are equal (i.e. no discourse can be considered as privileged one), there exist an essential difference between P-discourse on one hand and M and O discourses on the other. M and O discourses are developed in the frame of science. Both of them have quite definite object (molecular structures or organism) and include research procedures, which are supposed to be adequate to the object. Such procedures, in particular, are observation, description and explanation. P-discourse differs from the two others, because it cannot be based on the same research procedures. In fact, P-discourse even does not have an object. It refers to subject and so implies rather special methods of research. Cognitive science often tries to ignore the fact and consider the subject of cognition as an object of scientific research. Usual practice of this science is description and explanation of some mental or cognitive events. These events can really be treated in the same manner as physical events in the frame of M or O discourse. P-discourse, in particular, can include hypotheses and theories. However, it is impossible to include in the discourse any kind of observation. Empirical base of research consists of evidences of subjects about themselves. Interpretation of these evidences by researcher plays a role of observation. Therefore, research strategy, which is implied by P-discourse, must include elements of hermeneutic. This fact influences on all the body of cognitive science. Research activity, which incorporates P-discourse, cannot be ‘mere science’. The very use of P-grammar makes it ‘non-objective’, because researcher, using the grammar does not only explain an object, but also must understand a subject.



Наталия Смирнова (Россия). Феноменологическая концепция релевантности и ее значение для современной теории познания

Natalia M. Smirnova (Russia). Phenomenological Conception of Relevances and Its Influence on Contemporary Theory of Knowledge


In contemporary European culture human beings find themselves in postmodern condition. Postmodernism manifests itself by the “decline of the major narratives” (J.F. Lyotard) and the far-ranging cultural incompatibility. Furthermore, we are just facing the process of widening unbridgeable gap between different cultural communities within the same society. Human reason seems to have fallen into anemic syndrome of resigned weakness, and Homo sapiens have been rapidly transforming into Homo ludens. A game (or gamble) becomes a key metaphor of contemporary culture. It leads not only to the impoverishment of thought and soul, but also threatens to make meaningless both human life and contemporary culture in general. Moreover, it threatens the very essence of humanity because it challenges the most significant human values, which constitute human being as such. It leads to the conclusion, that when dealing with social and human problems it essential to pay due attention to the discourse of social thinking, which focuses on the meaningful structure of the social universe. It acquires crucial significance for social theory which seeks to find out of how people act, think and understand each others in everyday life. This is the question pertaining to all social sciences, and each of them has to contribute to its solution.

Phenomenological conception of the life-world in its various dimensions is just the case in point. Phenomenological ideas, applied to the social world, create a new paradigm in social thinking, aimed at the study of meaning sedimentation process, which constitutes the framework of human thought and activity, and eventually the meaningful structure of the social world. It therefore lays the deepest foundation for human understanding in social life.

The works of A. Schutz, esteemed father-founder of social phenomenology, has become increasingly known since publication in the Netherlands his Collected Papers. Its first volume, entitled “The problem of Social Reality”, appeared in 19621. The paper “Reflections on the Problem of Relevance”, on which we will focus our attention in this paper, has not been published during his lifetime. Its handwritten version has been discovered among his manuscripts only after his author’s death. Written between August 1947 and August 1951, it is supposed to be (according to R. Zaner) the first part of his five-part study, preliminary entitled “The world as Taken for Granted: Toward a Phenomenology of the Natural Attitude”. Part 1 bore the title “Preliminary Notes on the Problem of Relevance”. Although A. Schutz did not intend to publish this separate portion of his study as significant in its own right (but only as a part of a wider context), Prof. R. Zaner brought this piece of the study, left in a very rough form, into linguistically acceptable shape. So that, Reflections on the Problem of Relevance, edited, annotated and with an introduction of R. Zaner successfully appeared in 1970. And a few months ago it becomes available to a Russian-language reader. In the year 2004 it was published together with the other selected papers and my concluding remarks in the huge volume of the Russian edition of A. Schutz’s Selected Papers2. Since then A. Schutz’s studies, including his Reflections on the Problem of Relevance, became available not only to the narrow range of professionals, but also to a wide Russian audience. Now let me briefly outline the context of the study.

A. Schutz refers to (and subsequently adhered to) phenomenological tradition in philosophy which takes its clues from E. Husserl’s transcendental phenomenology. According to E. Husserl, philosophy is essentially a strict science. Investigation of the deepest presuppositions of human reason he believes should be the main thematic concern of transcendental phenomenology. But in contrast to E. Husserl, who brackets (or suspends of) natural attitude in the process of the so-called phenomenologically transcendental reduction, A. Schutz, facing not only the problems of epistemology or methodology of pure science, but also human understanding in the social world, makes the word in the so-called natural attitude the main subject of his concern.

In respect to the social world it turns out to be the question of constitutive phenomenology of the social world, that is, the study of the meaningful structure of the social world, which is the only able to throw a light on the question of what allows people to understand each other, or simply “what makes the social world tick”. In the context of the present study it is the question of cognitive foundation of the social world.

The attack on this problem is based upon two presuppositions, derived from phenomenology of natural attitude. They imply that:

- common-sense knowledge of everyday life consists of the constructs in its typicality, which form the life-world accepted beyond doubts;

- the life-world is essentially shared with the other individuals, living and acting in mutually interlocking activities.

The above-mentioned system of typicality constructs is largely taken for granted without questions (although they may be brought into question under certain circumstances). Following to M. Polaniy, it may be called “tacit knowledge”. Nevertheless, it implies that “taken-for-grantedness” remains out of questions (“unthematized”) within the framework of our “natural attitude”. In order to put them into questions we have to make thematic this natural attitude itself. Only in this way are we able to make explicit what is initially implicit (or taken for granted), - namely, the aabove-mentioned cognitive foundation of social reality. This is specifically phenomenological perspective of study the question of what does it mean to be “social” and what does it means to be “a world”. In this sense A. Schutz’s project is at the same time an effort to discover the deepest presuppositions of empirical social sciences. “The foundational analysis and explications of the “social”, “behavior” and the “human”, states R. Zaner, is necessarily fundamental to the determination of which methods and concepts are appropriate and justifiable”3. It implies, that phenomenology of the social world is the phenomenology of the social sciences at the same time.

A. Schutz’s study of relevance strictly follows the mainstream of his daily life structure investigations. His conception of relevance refers to the concept of the so-called multiple realities, derived from W. James’ work as it has been presented in 21th. chapter of his well-known Principles of Psychology4. Accordingly, multiple realities turn out to be the key notion and the basic principle of the life-world stratification.

The term “reality”, W. James insists, could hardly refer to the objective world as it exists beyond our consciousness, experienced and conceived. It rather designates our meaning of reality. He maintains that reality is nothing but the set of our sensual, emotional life and activities. Whatever attracts our interest becomes real, W. James bestows it “the accent of reality”. To call something real means to assert, that it captures our interest in this or that way. There are an infinitive number of reality strata, each of them having its own particular style of existence, way of presentation and degree of attention to life. In other words, they all are real after their own fashion. W. James calls them “sub-universes”. These sub-universes embrace the meanings of physical things, scientific ideal types and their relationships, religion, madness, realm of dreams, fantasy and so on. Living in one of them, we tend to obscure or even to forget the others, so there is not smooth traffic between the sub-worlds. And precisely for the reason of their relative autonomy and discrete existence E. Husserl designates them as “the units of sense”5.

W. James consciously restricted his analysis only to psychological aspects of “multiple realities”, investigating them in terms of beliefs and disbeliefs (in his The Fixation of Belief.) Nevertheless the father-founder of phenomenology E. Husserl highly appreciates W. James’ idea of multiple realities, because it paves the way to further investigations of the structure of human consciousness. But in contrast to W. James’ approach, he frees them of psychological implications. E. Husserl tries to contemplate the question not in terms of beliefs and disbeliefs, but rather in transcendentally phenomenological way, i.e. in terms pure consciousness structure. He uses it as a means for further elaboration of relationship between the theme and horizon, that is of thematic kernel and its surrounding horizon as they are given at any moment of our inner time.

A. Schutz goes far beyond both W. James’ psychological approach (“orders of reality”, sub-universes”) and even E. Husserl’s pure constitutive phenomenology (“sense-units”). But following Husserlian tradition to explore the ultimate presuppositions of each mental insight, he recognizes it as one of the most important philosophical question. He also releases the concept “sub-universe” from its psychological implications as well as bestows them the accent of reality by the name of “the finite provinces of meaning”. He prefers to speak about meanings rather then sub-universes in order to stress, that what he actually has in his mind is not ontological structure of the objects of outer space but rather the meaningful structure of the social world. The latter is essentially pluralistic, constituted by different kinds of human experiences. A. Schutz ascribes each of them its particular cognitive style, which has its specific degree of awakeness, tension of consciousness or attention to life, each of them being the highest in the province of everyday life. There is no paved way between the meaning provinces; the shift from one to another subjectively experienced as a shock or a leap. It is produced by the radical change of the way, in which each of them presents itself in inner time consciousness. It was precisely that point of view he adhered in On Multiple Realities.

In his further consideration the problem of multiple realities A. Schutz finds himself facing the following problems:

- cognitive boarders of the finite provinces of meaning;

- interrelations among the different provinces;

- which of them can be considered as “paramount” reality?

All these questions he inherited from W. James. But here are some new questions he raises:

- the way of constitutive activity which gives them rise;

- the typical way, in which they maintain themselves;

- what gives them the accent of reality or what makes them “real” at any particular moment.

While the former three questions he scrutinizes in his daily life investigations, the latter turn out to be the subject of his “Reflections on the Problem of Relevance”. It is precisely this study, which will be on the focus of my further reflections.

In his previous works A. Schutz concentrated his major attention upon the “province of working”, which he declared to be “the paramount reality”. Using E. Husserl’s terms, it was this particular realm of reality, which became thematic for the whole study. Putting forward the world of working and ascribing it its privileged position among the others had been substantiated by the references to the basic structure of human consciousness. The study on the world of working as governed by the system of relevance allowed him not only to shed important light on the essence of theme-horizon relationship in general, but also on the structure of human actions in the social world. The actions are supposed to have the center of space-temporal continuum, namely, my actual “Here” and “Now”, which compose my field of actions. The latter appears hierarchically organized in zones of actual, potential and restorable reach, the so-called “manipulatory sphere” being the center. Each of a zone has its own spatial and temporal horizons and structures, typically conceived. These interrelated zones of actual, potential and restorable experience form unquestioned but always questionable “world taken for granted”. It may also be seen as a cultural matrix of the world of working. Its initial presuppositions are: “I can do it again” as well as “And so forth and so on”.

The second basic assumption of A. Schutz’s conception of relevance is that at any moment I find myself in biographically determined situation. It is only partly defined by my actual experience. A. Schutz insists that my biographically determined situation is necessarily historical due to the fact, that it has to a large extent been formed by my previous sedimented experiences which I preserved in my memory. The outcome of my personal history constitutes my “stock of knowledge at hand” on which I rely any moment in my acts and thoughts. At the same time it is socially derived knowledge, which necessarily refers to the experience of the others.

A. Schutz tends to agree with W. James, that we are never equally interested in all strata of the world of working at the same time. It is just my pragmatic interest, which organizes and structures the world we live in, into the different spheres of importance. In other words, “the selective power of our interest” defines the spheres of major or minor intimacy and anonymity within my world of working. How I define situation, to what I pay attention depends on my pragmatic interest, which guides man within his natural attitude in daily life. It constitutes my “plan of action” or “project at hand”, prevailing on my “life plan” at any particular moment. And each project he stresses is determined by my pragmatic interest.

A. Schutz highly appreciated W. James’ idea of human mind’s selectivity, which guides man within his natural attitude in daily life. But in contrast to the author of Principles of Psychology he does not tend to root selective function of human mind exclusively in pragmatic motive. The concept “selective function of our interest” used by H. Bergson and W. James seems too ambiguous to designate the main idea, which A. Schutz actually has in his mind. Being derived from psychology of individuals, it is unable to describe the life-world which is essentially intersubjective. Trying to release the notion “interest” from its psychological implications, he changes it for relevance – just as he did changing James’ “sub-world” for the “province of meaning”. Moreover, he takes into account James’ idea of pragmatic justification reference to his particular philosophical background, namely, to philosophy of pragmatism. According to its basic assumptions, practical ratification of thought by actions in outer world should be regarded as the only criterion of truth. Accordingly, our physiological states are taking as explaining our feelings, and even the question legitimately arises, whether consciousness exists at all. But within the framework of phenomenology the various provinces of meaning or realms of reality are interconnected by the unity of our consciousness. Closer inspection reveals however, that although being psychological unity, I live in several of these realms simultaneously. Thus, when writing this text, I am involved at least in three different activities at the same time, namely, in thinking about A. Schutz’s contemplation on the problem of relevance, in using my PC program and in typing the text. Moreover, I am trying to put my thoughts in the language which is obviously foreign to me, namely in English. Taken together, all these activities (theoretical contemplation, writing in foreign language, typing, PC using) are subjectively experienced as a single activity undivided into the parts of different attention to life. But although experienced as a unity of actions, my present doing is not a single activity. To put it phenomenologically, I am actually involved at least in two meaning provinces simultaneously, that is in the world of working (pressing the buttons of my PC keyboard, looking through Russian-English dictionary, etc.) and in the world of theoretical contemplations, each with its own attention to life, dimension of time and particular articulation into thematic kernel and horizonal surrounding.

This is precisely the point, where A. Schutz deviates from W. James’ view, making a step further in Reflections. He insists, that “the theory concerning the mind’s selective activity is simply the title for a set of problems more complicated even then those of field, theme and horizon – namely, a title for the basic phenomenon we suggest calling relevance6. To think, that living in one province of meaning we may at any time change it for another (and its selection defines what is thematic in the field of consciousness) leads to oversimplification of the real state of affairs. It is very important to realize, he suggests in Reflections, that the levels of my personality are involved in several realms of reality simultaneously and to select one of them can merely mean, that we are making it our system of reference, the prevailing theme. In given example the simultaneously performed activities are of different degrees of intimacy in respect of nearness or distance of my personality. This heterogeneous set of activities is also structurized into its own theme and horizon. Typing the text and looking through the dictionary are to a great extent automatized. But making up the text by putting my thoughts into words is much more close to the kernel of my personality. Thus, only superficial levels of my personality are actually involved in such performances as habitual, routine and even quasi-automatic typing, while the deeper levels of my personality are involved in theoretical contemplations. In other words my paper preparation is certainly thematic, while the other activities, also important, seem to have been turned away to the horizon.

But actually all these activities have never “released from my grip”. A. Schutz insists that two different levels of our personality (both superficial and deeper) are simultaneously involved, the theme of the activity of one of them being reciprocally the horizon of the other, so the actualized theme receives the specific tinge from the other, which remains the hidden ground of the former. A. Schutz illustrates the point by the structure of music. Imagine two independent themes which are simultaneously going on in the flux of music. We may pursue one of them, taking it as the main theme, and the other as the subordinated one, or vice versa: one theme is leading while the other has never been released from our grip. And our consciousness, A. Schutz insists, is just similar to this. In the light of this study it essentially acquires counterpointal structure, which manifests the artificial split of our personality. It also implies, that theme, field, horizon and relevance are different when viewed subjectively (i.e. from the subject’s point of view) and objectively, that is from the observer’s point of view. Putting into play different levels of our personality (different tensions of consciousness and modes of attention to life, dimensions of time, degrees of anonymity and intimacy) “the counterpointal articulation of the themes and horizons pertaining to each of such levels (including finally the schizophrenic patterns of the ego) are all expressions of the single basic phenomenon: the interplay of relevance structures7.

Hence, it is just the system of relevance, which turns out to be one of the most significant A. Schutz’s concepts in his highly sophisticated theory of the life-world.

Now let me briefly outline the basic system of relevance, used in Reflections. There are 3 kinds of relevance described in Reflections: topical, imposed / intrinsic and interpretative relevance. Topical relevance appears to be the most important for the whole theory. By virtue of this relevance something is constituted as problematic in the unstructuralized field of unproblematic familiarity. It organizes the field into theme and horizon and segregates the former from unquestionable knowledge background which is simply taken for granted. Even though topical relevance is closely connected with the so-called “actual interest”, they must not be confused: while actual interest presupposes existence of the problem, topical relevance constitutes the problem itself. As far as the way of an unfamiliar experience is concerned, A. Schutz suggests that we should distinguish imposed relevance from the intrinsic relevance. If we do not thematize unfamiliar experience by means of the will (a voluntary act), we call this kind of relevance “imposed relevance”. For example, you find an unfamiliar object in the middle of your room. You have no intention to study it, but the object attracts your attention by its very unfamiliarity. There are many other kinds of imposed topical relevance. The experience of shock, which is peculiar to any shift of the attention from one province of meaning to another imposes new topical relevance; any nonvolitional change in the level of our personality, any change of relative intimacy to relative anonymity; any change in time-dimensions in which we live simultaneously imposes other topical relevance. In general, any interruption in smooth running the basic life-world idealizations such as “and so forth, and so on” as well as “I can do it again” creates imposed topical relevance. As usual topical relevance is imposed in the cause of social interaction.

But there exist some topical relevance which appears entirely different from those which are imposed. If we voluntary structure a field of perception into thematic kernel and horizon, we put into play intrinsic relevance. It has two subdivisions: the first one consists in enlarging or deepening the prevailing theme. The second implies the voluntary shifting attention from one topic to another, both of them being separate, i.e. without any connection between them. In the first case the original theme has been retained, and the original thematic kernel remains more or less related to the changed one. As E. Husserl reveals, each theme may be viewed as an unlimited field for further thematizations. It can be viewed as the locus of infinite number of topical relevance which may be developed by further thematization of the intrinsic content. Closer inspection reveals, however, that we put into play another level of our personality or change the interplay of time-dimensions in which we live simultaneously. Concerning the given example of nonimposed relevance it means, that what was previously horizontal has become thematic, but the new theme has not been created. Rather, the original theme has been modified in such a way, that previously horizontal and now thematic elements have become intrinsic to the theme. In the second case, i.e. in shifting to the completely different theme, the original theme has been abandoned. It is the case when I have completed my work or temporary put it off till next time; in such a case the original theme is no longer in my grip. Turning back to the first case we may see, that the original theme remains constant as determining factor of all further subthematizations. For this reason we may call it the paramount theme (by the analogy with paramount reality of daily life). Thus we may say that topical relevance is intrinsic to the paramount theme. The paramount theme is maintained as the home base, and all referential structures of the topical relevance derive their meaning from the intrinsic meaning of the maintained paramount theme. This particular system A. Schutz calls the intrinsic topical relevance in contrast to the imposed topical relevance. As we have seen earlier, it is characteristic of the imposed topical relevance, that the articulation into the theme and horizon is imposed by the emergence of an unfamiliar experience, by the shift of the attentional ray from one province of meaning to another, while in the system of intrinsic topical relevance we may or may not pay attention to the indications implicit in the paramount theme, that is we may or may not transform horizontal surrounding into thematic kernel.

An unfamiliar experience is thematically given to the interpretation. The latter may be seen as the process by means of which we grasp the meaning of what is now in the thematic kernel of the field. We have to subsume it under the various typical prior experiences which constitute our stock of knowledge at hand. But not all sedimented experiences are used as a scheme of interpretation. There are a few coherent types of previous experiences with which the present object may be compared, interrelated by sameness, likeness, similarity. We may call them relevant to interpreting the new set of experience. This kind of relevance is obviously different from topical relevance. A. Schutz calls it interpretative relevance. I can interpret, A. Schutz believes, by comparison typical moments of the percept with typical moments of my previous experiences. But what is relevant to the interpretation depends on both objective and subjective context. Supposing, I find a strange thing in the dark corner of the house. It is equally similar to both pile of rope and a snake. The guess “a pile of rope” is more plausible in sailor’s rather than in my own house. But if I find this object in my own house, A. Schutz suggests, I tend to interpret it “a snake”. If the object does not move, it enhances the plausibility, that it is lifeless. But hibernating snakes do not move either; so I do not succeed in trying to identify the unfamiliar object, since interpretatively relevant elements remain ambiguous and both interpretations of the same thematic object are obviously still plausible. Many authors, including E. Husserl, were inclined to treat the hesitation between doubtful interpretations as an oscillating between two themes. In contrast to this, A. Schutz suggests, that only one theme prevails throughout the whole process as paramount. What is thematic is always the percept of the same strange object in the corner of the room – an object of such-and-such shape, color and size. He insists, that “the noema8 of this percept remains unchanged, despite all possible noetical variations”9. But it is true, he argues, that in order to collect new interpretatively relevant elements intrinsic to the same thematic object, I must shift my attentional focus in such a way, that data, formerly horizontal, are drown into the thematic kernel. Nevertheless, in spite of all these variations the percept of the same object remains my home base, my paramount theme which is never out of grip10.

Interpretative relevance may be both imposed and intrinsic. The ambiguous guess which originates in the passive synthesis of recognition (in which the object perceived as “similar”, “like”, “of the type”) is certainly imposed. It lacks any volutional character. But as soon as problematic possibilities (as E. Husserl calls them) have been established as equally plausible interpretations of the same object, the additional interpretative relevance will be obtained by a volutional turning to the intrinsic elements of the paramount theme. In general, the interpretative relevance of my first guess is experienced as imposed, while examination of the plausibility of such interpretation originates in volutional activities. These activities transform the imposed relevant moments of the perceptual theme into intrinsic interpretative relevance. The “weight” of the outcome of the interpretation that is the degree of certainty which will satisfy me depends upon situation. If I hesitate to interpret the unfamiliar object as a pile of rope or a snake I need higher degree of certainty, than if I am in doubt, whether it is a pile of rope or a pile of clothes. But any interpretations remain tentative, subject to verification or falsification by supervening interpretatively relevant material.

Motivational relevance is neither topical nor interpretational. It does not presuppose the articulation of the field of consciousness into theme and horizon, because this field has remained unchanged. Nor does it refer to the interpretatively relevant material at hand. This kind of relevance refers to “in-order-to” and “because” motives. The dictionary defines motive as any idea, need, etc, that impels to action. But this definition covers two different situations, which have to be separated. On the one hand, it is an idea of the state of affairs to be brought about by the actions. The projected goal is phantasized before we start our action. It is the motive which inspires us “let’s go”! We act in order to bring about the projected state of affaires. A. Schutz calls this kind of motive “in-order-to-motive” of action. But if I place myself at the moment after my action has already begun, I may express the same situation by means of “because” sentences. In other words, the paramount project is motivationally relevant for the projecting of the single steps of action, the single steps to be performed are “causally relevant” for bringing about the desire result. In the given example I want to investigate the unfamiliar object because I fear that it is a snake. My fearing snakes is a genuine because-motive of my project of making a decision. Whereas “the in-order-to” relevance motivationally originates from the already established paramount project, “the because-of” relevance deals with the motivation for the establishment of the paramount project itself.

Motivational relevance may also be imposed or intrinsic. Choosing the paramount project seems intrinsically motivationally relevant. It originates in volutional act. All motivational relevances derived from the paramount project are experienced as being imposed.

All the above-mentioned relevances are interconnected with one another in many respects. Thus, the system of interpretational relevance may be motivationally relevant for building up of the new intrinsic topically relevant systems, while my motivational relevances are nothing but sedimentations of my previous experiences once topically or interpretationally relevant. It is greatly important to understand, A. Schutz insists, how the system of interpretational relevance functionally depends on the system of topical relevance. It is clear, that there are no interpretational relevances as such, but only interpretational relevances referring to the given topic. They are experienced as taken together.

E. Husserl points out, it is the act of reflection which brings the performed activity into view, it is necessarily artificial act, by means of which the flux of experiences can be grasp as such. The same is true for the systems of relevance. As A. Schutz maintains, that in our mental activities (or in a more wide context “working” activity as well) we are directed exclusively toward the theme of the field of consciousness, that is toward the problem we are concerned with, the object of our interest or attention, in short, toward what is topically relevant. Everything else is in the margin, in the horizon; the motives of our actions are also in the margin of the field, whether the motives to be “in-order-to” type or “because-of” type. And implicit in the inner and outer horizons of the topic are those elements which become interpretatively relevant to the ongoing activity of our mind as regards to the topically relevant thematic kernel11. I may obviously turn to what is implicit in these horizons and bring such elements into the thematic kernel. And this is very important for A. Schutz’s conception of relevance (in contrast to Husserl’s): I may shift my attentional focus without letting what is formerly topically relevant out of my grip. If I do keep it in grip, it continues to subsist as the main topic in relation to which the formerly horizontal elements (now brought into the thematic kernel), are constituted as subtopic or subthemes having manifold relations (foundedness, contiguity, modification and modalization) to the main theme. On the other hand, it is the prevailing system of motivational relevance (my “evoked interest”), which may lead to constitution of the new topical relevance: namely to investigate the atypical, the strange event, which interrupts smooth running daily life idealizations “And so forth, and so on” as well as “I can do it again”. If any counterproof invalidates the hitherto unquestioned course of experience, things cannot be taken for granted any longer. Finally, the newly created topical relevance may be the origin and starting point for a set of the new motivational relevances: formerly irrelevant may becomes interesting and is being constituted as a new topic or at least as subtopic. Though unfamiliar and hitherto irrelevant to me, it becomes motivationally relevant and worth to be investigated. In order to transform horizontal implications of the main topic into subtopics, I must modify my system of interpretational relevance. And the shift in the system of interpretational relevance becomes a starting point for a set of new motivational or topical relevances.

A. Schutz’s study of the interdependence of the three systems of relevance clearly reveals that neither of them can occupy the privileged position. Furthermore, interrelationships among the types of relevance are not at all chronological in a sense, that one of them is “the first”, and the other – “the second” etc. All three types are obviously experienced as inseparable, as an undivided unity, and their dissection into three types is the result of an analysis of their constitutive origin. Any of them may become the starting point for bringing about changes in the other two. Nevertheless, the distinction between the three may essentially contribute to the various problems of social philosophy and epistemology.

A. Schutz faithfully believes, that:

- the theory of the topical relevance will contribute to the concept of value and our freedom in selecting the values by which we wanted to be guided in our practical and theoretical life;

- the theory of interpretational relevance will throw a fresh light on the function and meaning of methodology and furnish the foundation of the theory of rationalization, and especially of the problem of verification, invalidation and falsification of propositions relating to the empirical facts; as well it will contribute to the constitutive problems of typicality.

- the theory of motivational relevance will be helpful for the analysis of problems related to personality structure and especially for the theory of intersubjective understanding.

A. Schutz himself did not obtain these results. But it seems very important, that the conception of relevances which he sophisticatedly developed in Relevances can not be viewed as complete and significant as such, but in its references to further problems. The author of Reflections himself clearly saw the obvious shortcomings of his theory of relevances. Thus he acknowledged, that he did not pay due attention to the problem concerning the emergent novel experience, i.e. the experience of absolutely unknown, which could not be grasped in its typicality. It is just the kind of experience which can become known only by radical modification of the whole system of relevances prevailing for the time being. However, it is always the meaning-context taken for granted which constitutes the framework of all possible future questions which might be interpretatively relevant to the topic and which becomes motivationally relevant for looking at the situation hitherto taken for granted12.

The novel experience, he suggests, have to fill a vacancy in our stock of knowledge at hand. The unfinished analysis of the problem of vacancies or enclaves (Leerstelle)13 seems through breaking, which leads to new dimensions in the theory of knowledge, or rather the theory of unknown. He intended to develop systematic theory of the vacancy and conceive the unknown by means of typicality of the vacancies14. It was thought to be phenomenological epistemology in the proper sense of the word. Is not the concept of vacancy and contour connected with the structurization into the theme and horizon? It may be supposed, that the shifting ray of attention is directed through the contours of the vacancies. Turning again to the example, that is hesitating between two possible interpretations (snake or pile of rope?), he raises the question: when are the given elements sufficient for interpretation? Or, using the newly introduced term: to what extent do the given elements predelineate the vacancies which remain undefined? Is there a kind of typicality which can be fitted to these vacancies? In this respect the process of knowledge can be conceived as filling-in vacancies of what is still not known, but these vacancies themselves are already typically predelineated through the contour-lines of what is already known. This is possibly a definition of the meaning-context which is of the clue significance for the study of the social world phenomenologically interpreted. But “hic egregie progressum sum”.


NOTES AND REFERENCES


Alfred Schutz, Collected Papers. The Hague, Martinus Nijhoff. Vol. 1, 1962. The Problem of Social Reality; vol. 2, 1964. Studies in Social Theory; vol. 3, 1966. Studies in Phenomenological Philosophy.

2 Russian translation: А. Шюц, Размышления о проблеме релевантности (пер. Н.М. Смирновой). В кн.: Альфред Шюц. Избранное: мир, светящийся смыслом. Москва, Росспэн, 2004. С. 235-398.

3 Richard M. Zaner. Editor’s introduction to: Alfred Schutz, Reflections on the Problem of Relevance. New Haven and London, Yale University press, 1970, p. XIII.

4 W. James. Principles of Psychology. New York, 1890. Vol. 2. Ch. 21, pp. 283-322.

5 See: Husserliana. New York, Macmillan, 1931. Sec. 55.

6 Alfred Schutz, Reflections on the Problem of Relevance. New Haven and London, Yale University press, 1970, p. 13.

7 Ibid., p. 15.

8 Following E. Husserl, A. Schutz uses the terms “noema” and “noesis”, which refer to “object-as-experienced” (noema) and the process of “experiencing-of-the-object” (noesis).

9 Alfred Schutz. Reflections on the Problem of Relevance, p. 41.

10 Ibid., p. 42.

11 Ibid., p. 67.

12 Ibid., p. 157.

13 This piece of the original manuscript concerning the brief sketch of a theory of “vacancy” was written in German and entitled “Philosophie der Leerstelle”.

14 The term “knowledge” has to be conceived in the broadest possible sense: not only in the sense of clarified and distinct knowledge, but as including all kinds of beliefs, from the unfounded blind beliefs to the well founded convictions.